9.
If then we have sufficiently discussed in their outlines the subjects of Happiness and of
Virtue in its various forms, and also Friendship and Pleasure, may we assume that the
investigation we proposed is now complete? Perhaps however, as we maintain, in the practical
sciences the end is not to attain a theoretic knowledge of the various subjects, but
rather to carry out our theories in action.
[
2]
If so, to
know what virtue is is not enough; we must endeavor to possess and to practice it, or in
some other manner actually ourselves to become good.
[
3]
Now if discourses on ethics were sufficient in themselves to make men virtuous,
‘large fees and many’ (as Theognis
1 says) ‘would they
win,’ quite rightly, and to provide such discourses would be all that is wanted.
But as it is, we see that although theories have power to stimulate and encourage generous
youths, and, given an inborn nobility of character and a genuine love of what is noble,
can make them susceptible to the influence of virtue, yet they are powerless to stimulate
the mass of mankind to moral nobility.
[
4]
For it is the
nature of the many to be amenable to fear but not to a sense of honor, and to abstain from
evil not because of its baseness but because of the penalties it entails; since, living as
they do by passion, they pursue the pleasures akin to their nature, and the things that
will procure those pleasures, and avoid the opposite pains, but have not even a notion of
what is noble and truly pleasant, having never tasted true pleasure.
[
5]
What theory then can reform the natures of men like these? To dislodge
by argument habits long firmly rooted in their characters is difficult if not impossible.
We may doubtless think ourselves fortunate if we attain some measure of virtue when all
the things believed to make men virtuous are ours.
[
6]
Now some thinkers hold that virtue is a gift of nature; others think we become good by
habit, others that we can be taught to be good. Natural endowment is obviously not under
our control; it is bestowed on those who are fortunate, in the true sense, by some divine
dispensation. Again, theory and teaching are not, I fear, equally efficacious in all
cases: the soil must have been previously tilled if it is to foster the seed, the mind of
the pupil must have been prepared by the cultivation of habits, so as to like and dislike
aright.
[
7]
For he that lives at the dictates of passion will
not hear nor understand the reasoning of one who tries to dissuade him; but if so, how can
you change his mind by argument?
And, speaking generally, passion seems not to be amenable to reason, but only to force.
[
8]
We must therefore by some means secure that the character shall have at the outset a
natural affinity for virtue, loving what is noble and hating what is base. And it is
difficult to obtain a right education in virtue from youth up without being brought up
under right laws; for to live temperately and hardily is not pleasant to most men,
especially when young; hence the nurture and exercises of the young should be regulated by
law, since temperance and hardiness will not be painful when they have become habitual.
[
9]
But doubtless it is not enough for people to receive the right
nurture and discipline in youth; they must also practice the lessons they have learnt, and
confirm them by habit, when they are grown up. Accordingly we shall need laws to regulate
the discipline of adults as well, and in fact the whole life of the people generally; for
the many are more amenable to compulsion and punishment than to reason and to moral
ideals.
[
10]
Hence some persons hold,
2 that while it is proper for the lawgiver to encourage and exhort men to virtue on
moral grounds, in the expectation that those who have had a virtuous moral upbringing will
respond, yet he is bound to impose chastisement and penalties on the disobedient and
ill-conditioned, and to banish the incorrigible out of the state altogether.
3 For (they argue) although the virtuous man, who guides his life
by moral ideals, will be obedient to reason, the base, whose desires are fixed on
pleasure, must be chastised by pain, like a beast of burden. This indeed is the ground for
the view that the pains and penalties for transgressors should be such as are most opposed
to their favorite pleasures.
[
11]
But to resume: if, as has been said, in order to be good a man must have been properly
educated and trained, and must subsequently continue to follow virtuous habits of life,
and to do nothing base whether voluntarily or involuntarily, then this will be secured if
men's lives are regulated by a certain intelligence, and by a right system, invested with
adequate sanctions.
[
12]
Now paternal authority has not the
power to compel obedience, nor indeed, speaking
generally, has the authority of any individual unless he be a king or the like; but law on
the other hand is a rule, emanating from a certain wisdom and intelligence, that has
compulsory force. Men are hated when they thwart people's inclinations, even though they
do so rightly, whereas law can enjoin virtuous conduct without being invidious.
[
13]
But
Sparta appears to be
the only or almost the only state in which the lawgiver has paid attention to the nurture
and exercises of the citizens; in most states such matters have been entirely neglected,
and every man lives as he likes, in Cyclops
fashion ‘laying down the law For children and for spouse.’
4
[
14]
The best thing is then that there should be a proper system of public regulation; but
when the matter is neglected by the community, it would seem to be the duty of the
individual to assist his own children and friends to attain virtue, or even if not able to
do so successfully,
5 at all events to make
this his aim. But it would seem to follow from what has been said before, that he will be
more likely to be successful in this if he has acquired the science of legislation. Public
regulations in any case must clearly be established by law, and only good laws will
produce good regulations; but it would not seem to make any difference whether these laws are
written or unwritten, or whether they are to regulate the education of a single person or
of a number of people, any more than in the case of music or athletics or any other form
of training. Paternal exhortations and family habits have authority in the household, just
as legal enactments and national customs have authority in the state, and the more so on
account of the ties of relationship and of benefits conferred that unite the head of the
household to its other members: he can count on their natural affection and obedience at
the outset.
[
15]
Moreover individual treatment is better than
a common system, in education as in medicine. As a general rule rest and fasting are good
for a fever, but they may not be best for a particular case; and presumably a professor of
boxing does not impose the same style of fighting on all his pupils. It would appear then
that private attention gives more accurate results in particular cases, for the particular
subject is more likely to get the treatment that suits him. But a physician or trainer or
any other director can best treat a particular person if he has a general knowledge of
what is good for everybody, or for other people of the same kind: for the sciences deal
with what is universal, as their names
6 imply.
[
16]
Not but what
it is possible no doubt for a particular individual to be successfully treated by someone
who is not a scientific expert, but has an empirical knowledge based on careful
observation of the effects of various forms of treatment upon the person in question; just
as some people appear to be their own best doctors, though they could not do any good
to someone else. But nevertheless it would
doubtless be agreed that anyone who wishes to make himself a professional and a man of
science must advance to general principles, and acquaint himself with these by the proper
method: for science, as we said, deals with the universal.
[
17]
So presumably a man who wishes to make other people better
(whether few or many) by discipline, must endeavor to acquire the
science of legislation—assuming that it is possible to make us good by laws. For
to mold aright the character of any and every person that presents himself is not a task
that can be done by anybody, but only (if at all) by the man with
scientific knowledge, just as is the case in medicine and the other professions involving
a system of treatment and the exercise of prudence.
[
18]
Is not then the next question to consider from whom or how the science of legislation can
be learnt? Perhaps, like other subjects, from the experts, namely the politicians; for we
saw
7 that legislation who is a
branch of political science. But possibly it may seem that political science is unlike the
other sciences and faculties. In these the persons who impart a knowledge of the faculty
are the same as those who practice it, for instance physicians and painters; but in
politics the sophists, who profess to teach the science, never practice it. It is
practiced by the politicians, who would appear to rely more upon a sort of empirical skill
than on the exercise of abstract intelligence; for we do not see them writing or lecturing
about political principles (though this might be a more honorable employment than
composing forensic and parliamentary speeches), nor yet do we notice that they
have made their own sons or any others of their friends into statesmen.
[
19]
Yet we should expect them to have done so had they been able, for they
could have bequeathed no more valuable legacy to their countries, nor is there any quality
they would choose for themselves, and therefore for those nearest to them, to possess, in
preference to political capacity. Not that experience does not seem to contribute
considerably to political success; otherwise men would never have become statesmen merely
through practical association with politics; so it would appear that those who aspire to a
scientific knowledge of politics require practical experience as well as study.
[
20]
On the other hand those sophists who profess to teach politics
are found to be very far from doing so successfully. In fact they are absolutely ignorant
of the very nature of the science and of the subjects with which it deals; otherwise they
would not class it as identical with, or even inferior to, the art of rhetoric.
8 Nor would they imagine that it is easy to frame a constitution by making a
collection of such existing laws as are reputed to be good ones, on the assumption that
one can then select the best among them; as if even this selection did not call for
understanding, and as if to judge correctly were not a very difficult task, just as much
as it is for instance in music. It is only the experts in an art who can judge correctly the productions of that art, and who
understand the means and the method by which perfection is attained, and know which
elements harmonize with which; amateurs may be content if they can discern whether the
general result produced is good or bad, for example in the art of painting. Laws are the
product, so to speak, of the art of politics; how then can a mere collection of laws teach a
man the science of legislation, or make him able to judge which of them are the best?
[
21]
We do not see men becoming expert physicians from a
study of medical handbooks. Yet medical writers attempt to describe not only general
courses of treatment, but also methods of cure and modes of treatment for particular sorts
of patients, classified according to their various habits of body; and their treatises
appear to be of value for men who have had practical experience, though they are useless
for the novice. Very possibly therefore collections of laws and constitutions may be
serviceable to students capable of studying them critically, and judging what measures are
valuable or the reverse, and what kind of institutions are suited to what national
characteristics. But those who peruse such compilations without possessing a trained
faculty cannot be capable of judging them correctly, unless they do so by instinct, though
they may very likely sharpen their political intelligence.
[
22]
As then the question of legislation has been left uninvestigated by previous thinkers, it
will perhaps be well if we consider it for ourselves, together with the whole question of
the constitution of the State, in order to complete as far as possible our philosophy of
human affairs.
[
23]
We
9 will begin then by attempting
a review of any pronouncements of value contributed by our predecessors in this or that
branch of the subject; and then on the basis of our collection of constitutions
10 we will
consider what institutions are preservative and what destructive of states in general, and
of the different forms of constitution in particular, and what are the reasons which cause
some states to be well governed and others the
contrary. For after studying these questions we shall perhaps be in a better position to
discern what is the best constitution absolutely, and what are the best regulations, laws,
and customs for any given form of constitution. Let us then begin our discussion.